WILLFUL BLINDNESS - DELIBERATE IGNORANCE:
Toronto lawyer Allan Rouben summarizes wilful blindness
in greater detail;
Liability for
criminal conduct requires an intent to cause harm. An important question in
criminal law is the degree to which lesser states than actual knowledge can
form the basis for a criminal conviction. In the decision of the Supreme Court
of Canada in R. v. Briscoe, 2010 SCC 13 released today, the Court makes
some important observations about the concept of wilful blindness:
“Wilful blindness
does not define the mens rea required for particular offences. Rather, it can
substitute for actual knowledge whenever knowledge is a component of the mens
rea. The doctrine of wilful blindness imputes knowledge to an accused whose
suspicion is aroused to the point where he or she sees the need for further
inquiries, but deliberately chooses not to make those inquiries. See Sansregret
v. The Queen, [1985] 1 S.C.R. 570, and R. v. Jorgensen, [1995] 4
S.C.R. 55. As Sopinka J. succinctly put it in Jorgensen (at para. 103),
“[a] finding of wilful blindness involves an affirmative answer to the
question: Did the accused shut his eyes because he knew or strongly suspected
that looking would fix him with knowledge?”
Courts and
commentators have consistently emphasized that wilful blindness is distinct
from recklessness. The emphasis bears repeating. As the Court explained in Sansregret
(at p. 584):
. . . while
recklessness involves knowledge of a danger or risk and persistence in a course
of conduct which creates a risk that the prohibited result will occur, wilful
blindness arises where a person who has become aware of the need for some
inquiry declines to make the inquiry because he does not wish to know the
truth. He would prefer to remain ignorant. The culpability in recklessness
is justified by consciousness of the risk and by proceeding in the face of it,
while in wilful blindness it is justified by the accused’s fault in deliberately
failing to inquire when he knows there is reason for inquiry. [Emphasis
added.]
It is important to
keep the concepts of recklessness and wilful blindness separate. Glanville
Williams explains the key restriction on the doctrine:
The rule that
wilful blindness is equivalent to knowledge is essential, and is found
throughout the criminal law. It is, at the same time, an unstable rule, because
judges are apt to forget its very limited scope. A court can properly find
wilful blindness only where it can almost be said that the defendant actually knew.
He suspected the fact; he realised its probability; but he refrained from
obtaining the final confirmation because he wanted in the event to be able to
deny knowledge. This, and this alone, is wilful blindness. It requires in
effect a finding that the defendant intended to cheat the administration of
justice. Any wider definition would make the doctrine of wilful blindness
indistinguishable from the civil doctrine of negligence in not obtaining
knowledge. [Emphasis added.]
Professor Don
Stuart makes the useful observation that the expression “deliberate ignorance”
seems more descriptive than “wilful blindness”, as it connotes “an actual
process of suppressing a suspicion”. Properly understood in this way, “the
concept of wilful blindness is of narrow scope and involves no departure from
the subjective focus on the workings of the accused’s mind” (Canadian
Criminal Law: A Treatise (5th ed. 2007), at p. 241). While a failure to
inquire may be evidence of recklessness or criminal negligence, as for example,
where a failure to inquire is a marked departure from the conduct expected of a
reasonable person, wilful blindness is not simply a failure to inquire but, to
repeat Professor Stuart’s words, ‘deliberate ignorance’.”
No comments:
Post a Comment